Skip to main content

Husserl (and Brentano) on Hume’s Notion of the Self

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Hume on the Self and Personal Identity

Part of the book series: Philosophers in Depth ((PID))

  • 224 Accesses

Abstract

Hynek Janoušek turns to the phenomenological tradition and Husserl’s Logical Investigations. Husserl’s phenomenology does not include either a unitary experienced self or a Kantian transcendental self, and he describes the self as a bundle. Husserl’s discussions of Hume form part of a wider appreciation of Hume in the German speaking world at the end of the nineteenth and beginning of the twentieth century. There are, however, important differences between the constituents of our bundles for Hume and Husserl. For Husserl, the conscious contents of experience have intentionality, that is, they are experienced as directed at pumpkins and pencils, trees and patches of red, whereas for Hume, such impressions and ideas are described according to their intrinsic character. In the second edition of Logical Investigations, Husserl abandons Hume entirely, as he there comes to accept the existence of a pure unitary ego.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Kuehn (2005, 134–137) and Janoušek and Zahavi (2020, 619–631).

  2. 2.

    I will also use the abbreviation LI for his Logical Investigations.

  3. 3.

    ‘A’ in front of the page number refers to the page number of the first German edition of the Logical Investigations as given in the critical edition of the work (Husserl 1984). If there is no page number of the English translation (Husserl 2001) given, the translation is mine since the text quoted or referred to is omitted from the English translation.

  4. 4.

    Husserl changed his mind concerning the topic of the self in the second edition of the book. Since the English translation of the Logical Investigations follows the second edition, the whole change of view is lost to the English reader.

  5. 5.

    See Husserl (1984, A328, 2001, 84).

  6. 6.

    Husserl’s phenomenology is not a reaction to Brentano’s later, reistic development of his theory. This development is captured in the posthumous editions of Brentano’s manuscripts Die Abkehr vom Nichtrealem (Brentano 1952) and The Theory of Categories (Brentano 1981).

  7. 7.

    I will also use ‘PES’ as an abbreviation of the full title.

  8. 8.

    According to Brentano, all psychical phenomena are intentionally related to an object. Besides being intentionally related to an object, all psychical phenomena also perceive themselves. Brentano calls this self-perception ‘inner perception’ (1973, 70, 98).

  9. 9.

    I am following the translation of ‘psychische Phänomene’ as ‘psychical phenomena’, instead of ‘mental phenomena’ used in the original translation.

  10. 10.

    I would like to thank Robin Rollinger for making the passage from manuscript Ps 53 and its English translation available to me. ‘Divisiva’ are parts at which we can arrive only by dividing a concrete whole into its constituents. Such parts are not things ‘in and of themselves’ (Brentano 1973, 120; editor’s footnote). For a somewhat different evaluation of Brentano’s view of Hume’s idea of the self as a bundle, see Textor (2013). For further discussion of Brentano’s theory of the unity of consciousness, see Fréchette (2015) and Dewalque (2017).

  11. 11.

    It is important to note that when Brentano writes that ‘there is no such thing as the soul’ (1973, 8) he is not referring to his own views but to views commonly associated with the nineteenth century ‘psychology without the soul’. This wasn’t his view. In his lectures on immortality in 1869–70 Brentano claimed that ‘experience offers the concept of the soul everywhere. In every one of our perceptions it is co-grasped’ (1869, 29679; see Rollinger forthcoming). This seems to be a view to which Brentano firmly held. However, this view implies that we can explicate what is a soul (the one unitary thing), and, if it is indeed a substance, what we actually mean by substance. For Brentano, this involves metaphysical investigations.

  12. 12.

    Cf. ‘As to immortality, it is precisely as easy to conceive that a succession of feelings, a thread of consciousness, may be prolonged to eternity, as that a spiritual substance for ever continues to exist: and any evidence which would prove the one, will prove the other’ (Mill 1872, 246).

  13. 13.

    Later in his career, Brentano changed his view, accepting that a group of real things is itself a real thing. However, for Brentano a group as a thing cannot be a unitary thing in and of itself; therefore, consciousness cannot be a group.

  14. 14.

    He nevertheless uses the phrase ‘substantive unity’ in one place to characterize what is revealed in inner perception (see Brentano 1973, 130).

  15. 15.

    Since an intentional relation is always a relation to something, this something must be presented. Since, for Brentano, all psychical phenomena are intentional, they must be either presentations or based on presentations.

  16. 16.

    Brentano means to say that the cause could be replaced by another one which is not a presentation.

  17. 17.

    Textor (2013, 79–80) finds another option insofar as two independent perceptual phenomena (of e.g. hearing and seeing) could contribute to a non-inferential comparative judgement affirming hearing and seeing. It is not clear to me how this judgement could be evident, as Brentano wants it to be, and how the consciousness of ‘and’ (or consciousness of the togetherness of phenomena) could arise. If it is constituted by the non-inferential judgement then it seems to me that what we have here is a peculiar version of a higher-order theory of consciousness.

  18. 18.

    However, for Husserl, the present phase of experience is not complemented by past and anticipated experiences describable as objects of our present memory and present anticipatory imagination, as Brentano would have it. Rather ‘retention’ and ‘protention’ are modes of experiences unified with ‘urimpressions’, that is, with experiences given in the ‘present now’. Living presence of retention, urimpression, and protention is thus not to be confused with the coexistence of experiences in the present now.

  19. 19.

    Husserl calls this unified complex of experiences a ‘phenomenological ego’ or ‘phenomenologically reduced ego’. This is a bit confusing, because, as we will see, Husserl claims that the stream of consciousness is anonymous.

  20. 20.

    This question makes no sense from the standpoint of Husserl’s later transcendental idealism. It is therefore omitted from the second edition of LI.

  21. 21.

    See also Janoušek and Zahavi (2020, 622–626).

  22. 22.

    This was the view of Jean-Paul Sartre who, in his Transcendence of the Ego, took himself to be developing Husserl’s early theory of the empirical ego (Sartre 2004, 3). For a Sartrean interpretation of Husserl’s early theory of consciousness, see Zahavi (2004, 32–44).

  23. 23.

    For a detailed explication of this passage from the standpoint of Husserl’s transcendental philosophy, see Marbach (1974, 74–121).

  24. 24.

    Lipps, Pfänder and Husserl engaged themselves with each other’s work and exchanged arguments on various topics—the nature of the self and of empathy being among the most important ones.

  25. 25.

    Lipps (1901, 12) stresses that this subjective awareness of the self as having an active, but limited influence on how objects appear is not of a reflective kind. The self as a conscious object is given only in a reflection on its past.

  26. 26.

    For a discussion of this type of objection, see Penelhum (1976, 12–15).

  27. 27.

    According to Smith (2003, 109), it was not until the beginning of the nineteenth century that philosophers such as Fichte or Maine de Biran began to realize this principal difficulty of Hume’s concept of the self. However, even before Hume, George Berkeley tackled a similar problem (see Hill 2018).

  28. 28.

    For a somewhat different, but related worry, formulated from the standpoint of Hume scholarship, see Penelhum (1992).

Bibliography

  • Brentano, F. (1869) Über die Unsterblichkeit der Seele. Unpublished manuscript LS 23. Harvard: Houghton Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874a) Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874b) ‘Drittes Buch: Von den Vorstellungen’. Unpublished manuscript Ps 53. Harvard: Houghton Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1952) Die Abkehr vom Nichtrealen. Briefe und Abhandlungen aus dem Nachlass, ed. Franziska Mayer-Hillebrand. Bern: Francke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1973) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, tr. A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1981) The Theory of Categories, tr. R. Chisholm and N. Guterman. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1995) Descriptive Psychology, tr. B. Müller. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewalque, A. (2017) ‘Brentano’s Mind: Unity Without Simplicity’, Rivista di filosofia, 108(3), 349–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fréchette, G. (2015) ‘Brentano’s Soul and the Unity of Consciousness’, Argumentos, 7(13), 65–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, J. (2018) ‘The Active Self and Perception in Berkeley’s Three Dialogues’ in Berkeley’s Three Dialogues: New Essays, ed. S. Storrie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960) Cartesian Meditations. An Introduction to Phenomenology, tr. D. Cairns. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1982) Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, tr. F. Kersten. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984) Logische Untersuchungen, Zweiter Band, Erster Teil, Husserliana, Band XIX/1, ed. Ursula Panzer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001) Logical Investigations, vol. 2, tr. J. N. Findlay. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2019) First Philosophy, tr. S. Luft, and T. M. Naberhaus. Dordrecht: Springer Nature.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janoušek, H., and Zahavi, D. (2020) ‘Husserl on Hume’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 28(3), 615–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuehn, M. (2005) ‘The Reception of Hume in Germany’ in The Reception of David Hume in Europe, ed. P. Jones. London: Thoemmes Continuum, 98–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipps, T. (1901) Das Selbstbewusstsein, Empfindung und Gefühl. Wiesbaden: Bergmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marbach, E. (1974) Das Problem des Ich in der Phänomenologie Husserls. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1872) An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy. London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penelhum, T. (1976) ‘The Self in Hume’s Philosophy’, The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, 7(2), 9–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penelhum, T. (1992) ‘The Self of Book 1 and the Selves of Book 2’, Hume Studies, 18(2), 281–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfänder, A. (1904) Einführung in die Psychologie. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rollinger, R. (forthcoming) ‘Franz Brentano on the Errors of Mach’s Positivism’ in Brentano and the Positive Philosophy of Comte and Mill, ed. I. Tănăsescu, A. Bejinariu, S. Krantz Gabriel, and C. Stoenescu. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1992) Being and Nothingness, tr. H. E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (2004) The Transcendence of the Ego, tr. A. Brown. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. (2003) Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to Husserl and the Cartesian Meditations. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Textor, M. (2013) ‘Unity Without the Self: Brentano on the Unity of Consciousness’ in Themes from Brentano, ed. D. Fisette and G. Fréchette. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2004) Subjectivity and Selfhood. Investigating the First-Person Perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Janoušek, H. (2022). Husserl (and Brentano) on Hume’s Notion of the Self. In: O'Brien, D. (eds) Hume on the Self and Personal Identity. Philosophers in Depth. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-04275-1_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics