Skip to main content
Log in

Beyond Logical Pluralism and Logical Monism

  • Published:
Logica Universalis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Logical pluralism as a thesis that more than one logic is correct seems very plausible for two basic reasons. First, there are so many logical systems on the market today. And it is unclear how we should decide which of them gets the logical rules right. On the other hand, logical monism as the opposite thesis still seems plausible, as well, because of normativity of logic. An approach which would manage to bring a synthesis of both logical pluralism and logical monism is called for. I review the possible forms of logical pluralism and render them more plausible. I thus arrive at logical dynamism, a synthesis of various pluralisms and monism focused on how logic develops.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Quine himself on the following and much less quoted pages admits that one can, of course, consciously propose changing the subject and provide reasons for such a change. Yet I think it is fair to concur with him that most of the deviant logicians understand their proposals differently, as not changing the subject. Thus, if Quine’s thesis that change of logic amounts to a change of subject were right, they fall prey to a misconception and cause a misunderstanding in the debates.

  2. The open-endedness of logical vocabulary, as well as of many other vocabularies of natural language, is more appropriately to be regarded as quite a fortunate property, as it allows our language to be flexible and adapt to the situations and challenges we actually face. But that would be a topic for a different debate.

  3. In [20].

  4. See pp. 78–79 in [1].

  5. Brandom provides the most thorought exposition of logical expressivism in [5]. A shorter introduction can be read in [6].

  6. In fact, according to Brandom’s inferentialism, on the background of which he proposes also logical expressivism, the meaning of a given expression consists precisely in the inference rules it is submitted to. Although I myself agree with it, I will not dwell on defending this general inferentialist understanding of meaning here. It is enough for the present purposes to acknowledge that inference rules are an important part of the meaning of all expressions. This view, I believe, should be acceptable for most philosophers of language.

  7. A non-controversial example is not easy to find here, yet perhaps we can say that in previous centuries, people used the word justice slightly differently than we do. Some behaviour which we consider as unjust was considered as just by our ancestors and vice versa. Maybe, they would even tend to define justice little bit differently then we would. Still, it is quite natural to say that we talk about the same thing, namely about justice and that the concept has somewhat developed. It would be much more stretched to claim that the concept has been replaced by a new one, at least if the differences are not all too great between our ancestors and us.

  8. The dots on the side of the word signify, for Sellars, the role the given expression plays in the whole of the language, a role which is common, for example to English words and their adequate German translations. But this peculiar feature of Sellars’ notation and thought, however valuable in itself, does not have to be dwelled upon here.

  9. Hardly ever does not mean never in general and maybe even in our particular case. The field of logical systems is so vast that virtually nothing can be claimed without exceptions or provisos. Polish logicians, inspired by ideas of Lukasiewicz, have developed the refutation systems, which are supposed to, contrary to the logical consequence relation according to the established orthodoxy, not bring us from true premisses to to true conclusions but rather from false or refuted premises to false or refuted conclusions. The basic ideas on which this approach is based were presented already in [16] and then rigorously developed in [23]. The history of these attempts is nicely summed up in [25] where the authors argue that refutation systems model the methods of falsification of a hypothesis in empirical science (see pp. 179–180). [4] offers a particularly straightforward example of such a refutation system, namely the anti-classical system in which a formula is consequence of a given set of premisses if and only if it is not a consequence in classical logic. Obviously, for a consistent set \(\Gamma \) we then have \(\Gamma \models \lnot \phi \) in the anti-classical system when we have \(\Gamma \models \phi \) in classical logic. This might be regarded as a counterexample to what I claim that hardly ever is the case. But besides the fact that hardly ever does not mean never, I can also defend my assertion by noting that although the logical symbols including negation can develop in multifarious and in general unpredictable manners, this does not mean that anything goes. Negation can have many flavours but it hardly makes sense to call the \(\lnot \) sign of the anti-classical system a negation. The authors of [4] (p. 6) themselves deny that it is a(seemingly paraconsistent) negation, claiming that the usage of the symbol \(\lnot \) merely reminds us of the origin of the new operator which is defined by means of the classical negation. I thank the anonymous referee for making me aware of the refutation systems.

  10. See p. 76 of [2].

  11. This article was supported by grant 17-15645S Logical models of reasoning and argumentation in natural language, led by Jaroslav Peregrin from Czech Academy of Sciences.

References

  1. Beall, J.C., Restall, G.: Log. Pluralism. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2006)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Beziau, J.-Y.: Logica universalis. In: Childers, T., Majer, O. (eds), Logica’94—Proceedings of the 8th International Symposium (1994)

  3. Beziau, J.-Y.: From consequence operator to universal logic: a survey of general abstract logic. In: Beziau, J.-Y. (ed.) Logica Universalis: Towards a General Theory of Logic. Birkhäuser, Basel (2005)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Beziau, J.-Y., Buchsbaum, A.: Let us be antilogical: anti-classical logic as a logic. In: Moretti, A., Moktefi, A., Schang, F. (eds.) Soyons logiques/Let us be logical. College Publications, Boston (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Brandom, R.: Making it Explicit. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Brandom, R.: Articulating Reasons. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Carnap, R.: Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache. Erkenntnis 2(1), 219–241 (1931)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Carnap, R.: Logische Syntax der Sprache. Springer, Wien (1934). transl. The Logical Syntax of Language, London: Kegan, Paul, Trench Teubner & Cie (1937)

  9. Cook, R.: Let a thousand flowers bloom: a tour of logical pluralism. Philos. Compass (2010). https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00286.x

    Google Scholar 

  10. Došen, K.: Logical constants as punctuation marks. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 30(3), 362–381 (1989). https://doi.org/10.1305/ndjfl/1093635154

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Eklund, M.: Making sense of logical pluralism. Inquiry Interdiscip. J. Philos. (2017). https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2017.1321499

    Google Scholar 

  12. Field, H.: Pluralism in logic. Rev. Symb. Logic 2(2), 342–359 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1017/S1755020309090182

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Hacking, I.: What is logic? J. Philos. 76(6), 285–319 (1979). https://doi.org/10.2307/2025471

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Harman, G.: Change in View. MIT Press, Cambridge (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Kripke, S.: Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Lukasiewicz, J.: Logika dwuwartosciowa. Przeglad Filozoficzny 23(1), 189–205 (1921). English translation: Two-valued logic. In: Lukasiewicz, J.: SelectedWorks (L. Borkowski, Ed.). North-Holland Publication, Amsterdam (1970)

  17. Peregrin, J.: Inferentialism: Why Rules Matter. Palgrave Macmillan, London (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Priest, G.: Revising logic. In: Rush, P. (ed.) The Metaphysics of Logic, pp. 211–223. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2014). https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139626279.016

    Google Scholar 

  19. Quine, W.V.O.: Philos. Logic. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Restall, Greg: Carnap’s tolerance, language change and logical pluralism. J. Philos. 99(8), 426–443 (2002). https://doi.org/10.1.1.38.3711

  21. Sellars, W.: Meaning as functional classification. Synthese 27(3), 417–437 (1974). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00484606

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Sher, G.: The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint. MIT Press, Cambridge (1991)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Slupecki, J.: Funkcja lukasiewicza. (The Lukasiewicz function). Zeszyty Naukowe Uniwersytetu Wroclawskiego (Publications of the Wroclaw University), Matematyka-Fizyka-Astronomia II 23(3), 33–40 (1959)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Tarski, A.: What are logical notions? Hist. Philos. Logic 7(2), 143–154 (1981). https://doi.org/10.1080/01445348608837096

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Waldmajer, J., Wybraniec-Skardowska, U.: On pairs of dual consequence operations. Log. Univ. 5(1), 177–203 (2011)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Williamson, T.: Semantic paradoxes and abductive methodology. In: Armour-Garb, B. (ed.) Reflections on the Liar. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2017)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Wittgenstein, L.: Philosophische Untersuchungen. Blackwell, Oxford (1953)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Zach, R.: Hilbert’s programme then and now. In: Jacquette, D. (ed.) Philosophy of Logic. Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, vol. 5, pp. 411–447. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2006). https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-044451541-4/50014-2

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pavel Arazim.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article was supported by Grant 17-15645S Logical models of reasoning and argumentation in natural language, led by Jaroslav Peregrin from Czech Academy of Sciences.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Arazim, P. Beyond Logical Pluralism and Logical Monism. Log. Univers. 14, 151–174 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-020-00253-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-020-00253-2

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation