Skip to main content
Log in

Enactive Ethics and Hermeneutics—From Bodily Normativity to Critical Ethics

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent enactive accounts of cognition have begun to disentangle social and normative aspects of the human mind. In this paper, we will contribute to this debate by developing an enactive account of moral development, i.e. the learning of ethical norms, and critical engagement with these norms through social affordances, participatory sense-making, and moral concern. The difficulty in articulating such an account is in reconciling the affective embodied aspects of moral experiences with the more orthodox aspects of ethics like critical reflection. In order to respond to this difficulty, we bring Ricoeur’s hermeneutics into dialogue with enactivism. Complementing the enactive tradition, we frame critical ethical learning as embodied interaction with diverse ethical dimensions allowing us to incorporate moral values in the form of critical narratives and the social imaginary. We agree with enactivist theories that participation and democratic dialogue are essential parts of critical reflection on ethical norms. Yet, we also contend that this kind of critical reflection benefits from hermeneutical interpretation, challenging larger participatory networks, such as social institutions, which nourish inequality and maintain unethical values.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We use “rational” as a broad category of cognitive processes that are supposedly free from affectivity, subjectivity, and relationality and are thus claimed to be superior for a broad range of moral cognizing. It is not our contention that cognitive capacities that are often labeled as rational do not exist, rather it is our contention that these capacities more organically scaffold onto and include affective, social, and relational dynamics.

  2. To be sure, we do not claim in this paper that hermeneutics would provice a full explanation of how critical learning of ethical values works. Nor does our paper claim to offer a fully-fledged account of critical ethical learning, which is not possible in one paper. Explaining into more detail critical learning—how human beings are capable of critically distancing themselves from prevailing values and norms—would require further research in developmental psychology. Our focus is not on developmental psychology, however, but on how certain hermeneutical concepts (e.g., narrative identity) invite to reflect on some of the issues an enactive understanding of critical ethical learning may run into.

  3. Those unfamiliar with participatory sense-making may imagine the simple example of two people in a canoe. They may start out learning to be reactive to each other, i.e., keeping the canoe from spinning as a result of uneven paddling. When the canoe breaks out to one side they may switch the side they are paddling on or correct with more forceful strokes. But as they get more skillful they begin to perceive their activity more of a joint activity. They become more attuned to smaller differences in the movement of the other and the canoe, and find a suitable rhythm and strength. As a result successful canoers will act in a way that their actions complement each other to maintain speed and course of the canoe. The magic of participatory sense-making is that they begin to negotiate a shared perspective on their environment. A particularly strong stroke by the other is no longer unexpected but understood as an indication to speed up or change direction. These kinds of interactions are ubiquitous as people negotiate areas of mutual activity with others: from simply steering a canoe to raising a child together.

  4. Noë provides an interesting account of aesthetics and critical engagement, arguing that “[a]esthetic experience happens against the background of criticism.” (Noë 2012, p. 126) Noë’s considerations may be partially transferable to the realm of morality. For example he concludes (ibid. 126–127) that “[…] the critical inquiry that the art work occasions and requires is the very means by which we exercise the understanding that brings the work of art into focus and so allows us to feel it, to be sensitive to it.” A conclusion that we would be sympathetic to in the realm of morality. However, Noë’s aspirations appear neither to work in the confines of enactive logic, nor to extend his considerations to morality, thus his account is only tangentially relevant to this paper. It is noteworthy, however, that Noë appears to rely very little on notions of participation or intersubjectivity, which are so critical to most approaches to enactive ethics. He also does not discuss the concept of social institutions, which as we will argue is also critical for an enactive understanding of ethics.

  5. We would like to point out again that it is not our intention in this paper to clain that hermeneutics offers a full account of how people are able to critically understand and distance themselves from existing social values. In order to develop such an account, psychological theories of moral development are needed. We nonetheless emphasize at this point that hermeneutics points out the importance of variations of and a critical attitude toward social imaginaries, in particular variations on opprossing imaginaries that are defended by ruling ideologies.

References

  • Adams S (2017) Ricoeur and Catoriadis in Discussion: On Human Creation, Historical Novelty, and the Social Imaginary. Rowman and Littlefield, London and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett NF (2017) The normative turn in enactive theory: An examination of its roots and implications. Topoi 36(3):431–443

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayliss AP, Frischen A, Fenske MJ, Tiper SP (2007) Affective evaluations of objects are influenced by observed gaze direction and emotional expression. Cognition 104(3):644–653

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann LT (2019) Emotions, experiments and the moral brain. The failure of moral cognition arguments against moral sentimentalism. Rivista internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 10(1):16–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann LT, Wagner J (2020) When push comes to shove—the moral fiction of reason-based situational control and the embodied nature of judgment. Front Psychol. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caracciolo M (2012) Narrative, meaning, interpretation: an enactivist approach. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 11(3):367–384

    Google Scholar 

  • Caracciolo M (2013) Blind Reading: Toward an Enactivist Theory of the Reader’s Imagination. In: Bernaerts L, De Geest D, Herman L, Vervaeck B (eds) Stories and Minds: Cognitive Approaches to Literary Narrative. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln, NE, pp 81–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Caracciolo M (2014) The Experientiality of Narrative: An Enactivist Approach. De Gruyter, Berlin and Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero A (2009) Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti G, Torrance S (2009) Emotion and ethics: an inter-(en) active approach. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 8(4):505–526

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher H (2013) Rigid and fluid interactions with institutions. Cogn Syst Res 25:19–25

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher H (2015) How we affect each other: Michel Henry’s “pathos-with” and the enactive approach to intersubjectivity. J Conscious Stud 21(1–2):112–132

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher H, Di Paolo E (2007) Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 6(4):485–507

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo E, Buhrmann T, Barandiaran XE (2017) Sensorimotor Life: An enactive proposal. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo EA, Cuffari EC, De Jaegher H (2018) Linguistic Bodies: On the Continuity between Life and Language. The MIT Press, Cambridge (MA)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dierckxsens, G. (2020) The Ambiguity of Justice: New Perspectives on Paul Ricoeur’s Theory of Justice, Leiden: Brill.

  • Froese T, Di Paolo EA (2009) Sociality and the life-mind continuity thesis. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 8(4):439–463

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2004) Hermeneutics and the cognitive sciences. J Conscious Stud 11(10–11):162–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2013) The socially extended mind. Cogn Syst Res 25–26:4–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2017) Enactivist Interventions: Rethinking the Mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Crisafi A (2009) Mental institutions. Topoi 28(1):45–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene JD (2014) Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between us and Them. Penguin press, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene JD (2015) Beyond point-and-shoot morality: why cognitive (neuro) science matters for ethics. Law Ethics Hum Rights 9:141–172

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (1996) Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108:814–834

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto DD (2007) The narrative practice hypothesis: origins and applications of folk psychology. R Instit Philos Suppl 60:43–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto DD, Myin E (2013) Radicalizing Enactivism. Basic Minds without Content. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto DD, Myin E (2017) Evolving Enactivism. Basic Minds Meet Content. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas H (1963) The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Harper and Row, New York City, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearney R, Treanor B (eds) (2015) Carnal Hermeneutics. Fordham University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana H, Varela F (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition. Reidel, Dordrecht, NL

    Google Scholar 

  • McGann M (2014) Enacting a social ecology: radically embodied intersubjectivity. Front Psychol 5:1321

    Google Scholar 

  • McGann M, De Jaegher H (2009) Self-other contingencies: Enacting social perception. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 8(4):417–437

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë A (2012) Varieties of presence. Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy V (2008) How Infants Know Minds. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur P (1992) Oneself as Another. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur P (2007a) From text to action: essays in hermeneutics II. Northwestern University Press, Evanston

  • Ricoeur P (2007b) From the moral to the ethical and to ethics. In: Pellauer D (ed) Reflections on the just. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 45–57

  • Schmidt MFH, Rakoczy H (2018) Developing an understanding of normativity. In: Newen Albert, de Bruin Leon, Gallagher Shaun (eds) Oxford Handbook of Cognition: Embodied, Embedded, Enactive and Extended. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Slatman J (2012) Phenomenology of bodily integrity in disfiguring breast cancer. Hypatia 27(2):281–300

    Google Scholar 

  • Sonnby-Borgström M (2002) Automatic mimicry reactions as related to differences in emotional empathy. Scandinavian J Psychol 43(5):433–443. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9450.00312

  • Strawson G (2004) Against narrativity. Ratio 17(4):428–452

    Google Scholar 

  • Urban P (2014) Toward an expansion of an enactive ethics with the help of care ethics. Front Psychol. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Grunsven J (2018) Enactivism, second-person engagement and personal responsibility. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 17(1):131–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1999) Ethical Know-How: Action, Wisdom, and Cognition. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ, Thompson E, Rosch E (1991) The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • von Uexkull J (1909) Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Springer, Berlin, DE

    Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll J (1934) Streifzüge durch die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen. In: O’Neil Joseph D (ed) A foray into the worlds of animals and humans. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN, p 2010

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Geoffrey Dierckxsens.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dierckxsens, G., Bergmann, L.T. Enactive Ethics and Hermeneutics—From Bodily Normativity to Critical Ethics. Topoi 41, 299–312 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-021-09790-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-021-09790-x

Keywords

Navigation